Ðåãèîíàëüíûé
ñîöèàëüíî-èííîâàöèîííûé óíèâåðñèòåò
Discourse Markers in Relevance Theory
(RT)
The
framework of Relevance Theory has produced quite a large amount of literature
on discourse markers since it provides an interesting pragmatic model for their
analysis.
Relevance
Theory (RT) builds from Grice’s ideas that speakers make use of principles or
maxims in conversations. That is a theory of pragmatics based on cognitive
principles. In this cognitive model, the effects of new information are worked
out by the hearers against the background of existing assumptions. Whilst a
cognitive environment is shared by all members of a speech community, the work
left for the hearers is to choose a context for an utterance so as to make the
correct inferences about the speaker’s meaning.
The
choice of context is constrained by the principle of optimal relevance: ‘Every act of ostensive communication
communicates the presumption of its own optimal relevance’. (1, p.158) The conversational aim to be
relevant is assessed with the principle that dispensable cognitive effort
should be avoided. Less cognitive effort means greater relevance.
Discourse
connectives (RT terminology) do not have a unitary semantic account. According
to Blakemore (2), some discourse connectives encode concepts, and others encode
procedures. These two types of meaning echo Austin’s distinction between
describing and indicating, and/or Grice’s distinction between saying and
conventionally implicating. This distinction between conceptual and procedural
meaning reflects a cognitive distinction between representation and
computation.
A
word with conceptual meaning contributes to the content of assertions. This
type of word encodes elements of conceptual representations. The information on
how these representations are to be used in inference is encoded by words with
procedural meaning.
Most
words encode concepts; for example teacher encodes
the concept TEACHER, or rich encodes the concept RICH. An example
of a discourse connective that encodes conceptual meaning would be the
following:
What I think we need, you see is a room
with a table, that is
to say, a table which
students could sit around. Blakemore (3, p. 328)
The
encoded meaning of table could be recovered as a concept of
something large for people to sit at, or the meaning could be recovered as the
concept of something smaller. The function of the reformulation indicated by that is to say in the example helps the hearer to
recover the first concept: a large item for students to sit at. The proposition
explicitly communicated by the reformulation is a proposition about the
conceptual representation that the hearer has to derive from the host
utterance.
Procedural
meaning cannot form part of the communicated message. The function of
procedural meaning is to guide the hearer towards the interpretation of a
message.
John is handsome, but he is always moaning.
But expresses that some
aspect of the interpretation of the second utterance contradicts an implication
derivable from the first. In the example, John has a good quality to be the
speaker’s love interest, that is, he is handsome. The fact that he is always
moaning contradicts the implication that he is a good candidate to be the
speaker’s love interest. But is a discourse connective encoding
procedures activating some kind of inference. The encoded meaning of discourse
connectives of this type is not part of the communicated message. The
communicated message is the result of the inferences triggered by these
discourse connectives.
The
function of discourse connectives is to guarantee that the correct context is
selected at minimal processing cost. Discourse connectives are valuable means
of constraining the interpretation of utterances whilst complying with the
principle of relevance.
According to Blakemore (4), there are three ways in which the
information of an utterance can be relevant: it may help to derive a contextual
implication; it may reinforce an existing assumption; or it may introduce
conflict to an existing assumption.
a. Max fell. David pushed him.
b. Pushing someone can cause the pushed item/person to fall.
(b) is a contextual implication derived from (a). Discourse connectives
can introduce contextual implications as well:
A: You drink too much.
B: So (what)?
In the following
examples the answer of speaker B is supposed to question the intended
relevance of what speaker A has just uttered. In fact, B is asking a rhetorical
question since speaker B has already drawn a conclusion regarding the
intentions of speaker A's utterance. Thus, a proposition introduced by the
discourse connective so has to be interpreted as a conclusion.
The information of an utterance can be relevant because it may
strengthen an existing assumption as in the following example:
a.
David isn’t here.
b.
We shall have to cancel the meeting.
c.
If David isn’t here, we shall have to cancel the meeting. (4, p.135)
The information in (a) is relevant to provide further evidence for the
assumptions in (b) and (c).
Some discourse connectives are concerned with strengthening. For
example, after all indicates that the proposition
introduced by it is evidence for an assumption that has just been made
accessible, as in the following example:
You
need to buy those shoes. After
all, they are gorgeous.
Other connectives that are concerned with strengthening according to
Blakemore are besides,
moreover, furthermore, also
(when utterance-initial), and indeed.
The information in an utterance can be relevant because it may
contradict an existing assumption as is the case in the following set of
utterances:
a. If Barbara is in town, then David
will be here.
b.
Barbara
is in town.
c. David isn’t here. (4, p.136)
The information in (c) is relevant because it contradicts and eliminates
the existing assumption in (a) when (b) is spoken by the hearer.
However is an example of a discourse
connective which introduce denials:
I
am not busy. However, I cannot speak to you.
However
indicates that the proposition it introduces, i.e., I cannot speak to you, is inconsistent with a proposition the
speaker assumes the hearer has derived as a contextual implication from the
first utterance. From the utterance I am not busy, the
hearer would derive that the speaker can speak to him/her.
The study of discourse connectives in RT is extensive. However, most of
the analyses so far have not been formalized in a syntactic or semantic manner.
Moreover, this type of analysis is rather difficult to formalize. RT makes
implicatures reliant both on individual memory organization and on indefinite
principles of processing effort that possibly differ across speakers and
hearers. Achieving general rules and predictions is problematic for a Relevance
theoretical account.
If
RT were formalized (there have been a few attempts so far), it is uncertain
whether the outcome would be insightful in a general theory concerning a
variety of issues such as how context affects the interpretation of
presuppositions, or explicate why there is wide agreement on their
interpretations.
The
first clash with this framework and our approach is that Blakemore (2) argues
that discourse markers do not have a function of markers of relationships or
connections between units of discourse. In our analysis, we will establish that
it is one of the crucial elements for the meaning of anyway, it relates two utterances or even a large group of them.
Bibliography:
1.
Dan Sperber and Deidre Wilson. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Blackwell,
Oxford, 1986.
2.
Diane Blakemore. Relevance and Linguistic Meaning. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 2002.
3. Diane Blakemore. Or- parenthicals, that is - parenthicals and the pragmatics of
reformulation. Journal of Linguistics, 43:311-339, 2007.
4. Diane Blakemore. Understanding Utterances. An Introduction to Pragmatics. Blackwell, Oxford, 1992.